眼睛看东西变形扭曲是什么原因| 为什么头发总是很油| 检查包皮挂什么科| 4月7日什么星座| 高血压吃什么好降压快| 后背酸痛是什么原因| 肠胃炎吃什么消炎药| 男人吃香菜有什么好处| np是什么| 高危型hpv66阳性是什么意思| 急性结肠炎什么症状| 信阳毛尖是什么茶| 83年属猪是什么命| 乙肝二四五阳性什么意思| 女人下面水多是什么原因| 什么解辣| 兔子能吃什么水果| 蚕丝衣服用什么洗最好| 肾阳虚有什么症状| 病人打白蛋白意味着什么| 兰桂坊是什么地方| 上半身胖属于什么体质| 强回声斑块是什么意思| 隐翅虫皮炎用什么药| 吃什么去湿气| 上海副市长什么级别| 什么是辛辣食物| 什么是爱呢| 嘴苦是什么原因引起的| 梦见自己拉了好多屎是什么意思| 男性前列腺炎有什么症状| 立冬和冬至什么区别| 翌字五行属什么| 美国什么时候建国的| 比是什么意思| 什么补铁| 为什么会起鸡皮疙瘩| 叶酸偏高有什么影响| 什么是高血脂| 尔尔是什么意思| 德国人是什么人种| 百白破是什么疫苗| 心绞痛是什么症状| 早上做什么运动最好| 血糖高吃什么可以降下来| 生意兴隆是什么生肖| 丧尽天良什么意思| 喝什么水最解渴| 丰衣足食是什么生肖| 保护心脏吃什么最好| 去胎毒吃什么最好| 为什么静脉曲张| 五脏是什么| ipadair2什么时候上市的| 什么是无性婚姻| 围绝经期吃什么药调理| 感染性腹泻吃什么药| 偶尔心慌是什么原因| 千什么一发| 高风亮节是什么意思| 芬太尼是什么| 什么药对伤口愈合快| 烈女怕缠郎是什么意思| 手肘发黑是什么原因| 什么是甲沟炎图片| 心病有什么症状| 如虎添翼是什么生肖| 安全期一般是什么时候| 膝关节积液是什么原因造成的| 菠萝蜜是什么季节的水果| 什么叫做亚健康| 食管裂孔疝什么意思| 爬山有什么好处| 氮泵是什么| 卵巢多囊症是什么原因造成| 张若昀原名叫什么| 野生铁皮石斛什么价| 盆腔炎检查什么项目| 射的快吃什么药| 古惑仔是什么| ecg是什么意思| 3月10日是什么星座| evian是什么品牌| 星期一左眼皮跳是什么预兆| smzco是什么药片| 女性尿道炎挂什么科| 拼音的音序是什么| 神奇的近义词是什么| 为什么不娶养猫的女人| 提篮子是什么意思| 不排大便是什么原因| 伪骨科是什么| 送锦旗有什么讲究| 恢复伤口吃什么好得快| 血小板分布宽度偏高是什么意思| 生鱼又叫什么鱼| cindy是什么意思| 蛇怕什么东西| 什么是生化| 什么是夫妻宫| 甲硝唑吃多了有什么危害| 蜂胶是什么| 梅毒阳性是什么意思| 财源广进是什么生肖| 已归档是什么意思| 什么时候怀孕几率高| 违心的话是什么意思| 你说到底为什么都是我的错| 双生痣是什么意思| 走路腿软没劲是什么原因引起的| 小孩指甲有白点是什么原因| 西洋参有什么功效和作用| 得道是什么意思| 9月16号是什么星座| 亭台楼阁是什么意思| 开会是什么意思| 张纯如为什么自杀| 雷达是什么| 尿液黄绿色是什么原因| 拉肚子吃什么蔬菜| x什么意思| 猫发烧吃什么药| 轻浮的女人是什么意思| 一桌餐是什么意思| 过敏性鼻炎吃什么药能快速缓解| 蛐蛐进屋有什么预兆| 肺炎不能吃什么东西| 孕妇羊水多是什么原因造成的| 皮肤糖化是什么意思| 共济失调是什么病| 怡什么意思| 世界上最贵的车是什么车| 腱鞘炎吃什么药| 1800年是什么朝代| 化疗和放疗有什么区别| 欧珀莱属于什么档次| 家中养什么鸟最干净| 喝老陈醋有什么好处| 打呼噜是什么原因引起的| 上吐下泻吃什么好| 罗飞鱼是什么鱼| 吃什么掉秤快| 医保卡是什么样子的| 什么样的马| 肾结石什么不能吃| 尿喝起来是什么味道| 高铁为什么没有e座| 警察两杠三星是什么级别| 蛋白尿是什么样子| 备孕叶酸什么时候吃最好| 鸡精和鸡粉有什么区别| amo是什么意思| 白酒是什么酿造的| 看见双彩虹有什么征兆| 榻榻米是什么| silk是什么意思| 反讽是什么意思| hpv吃什么药| 唇系带断了有什么影响| 掉头发是因为什么| 秋葵长什么样| 左侧头皮发麻是什么原因| 发烧不能吃什么东西| 肺气虚吃什么中成药| 轶是什么意思| 小腿发凉是什么原因造成的| 为什么心脏会隐隐作痛| 10年什么婚| 复原是什么意思| 万能输血者是什么血型| 宠幸是什么意思| 甘薯是什么东西| 儒家是什么意思| 高硼硅是什么材质| 都市丽人什么意思| 血钾高是什么引起的| 大姨妈喝什么好| 梦见下雪了是什么意思| 放屁多是什么原因呢| lee是什么意思| 这是什么牌子| 剪头发叫什么手术| 急性呼吸道感染是什么引起的| 大便陶土色是什么颜色| 姜为什么不能晚上吃| 抑郁症为什么会想死| 脑梗什么不能吃| 小妮子是什么意思| 体重什么时候称最准确| 血常规24项能查出什么病| 努力的意义是什么| r商标是什么意思| 文替是什么意思| 甲亢吃什么食物最好| 科伦是什么药| 势力是什么意思| 六味地黄丸适合什么人吃| 1221是什么星座| 很容易出汗是什么原因| 灵媒是什么意思| 胳膊脱臼什么症状| 老年人反复发烧是什么原因引起的| cacao是什么意思| 鼻炎吃什么药最好| 学海无涯苦作舟的上一句是什么| 软文什么意思| 汤姆是什么品种的猫| 黄色裤子配什么颜色上衣| 人皇是什么意思| 哺乳期可以吃什么消炎药| 家里停电打什么电话| 世界上最贵的狗是什么| 2b什么意思| 元参别名叫什么| instagram是什么| 甲鱼和什么一起炖最好| 大舅哥是什么意思| 宫颈那囊什么意思| 一对什么| 喜欢黑色的人是什么性格| 手五行属什么| 普洱属于什么茶| 和田玉对身体有什么好处| rop是什么意思| 男生第一次是什么感觉| 肝掌是什么原因引起的| 成人礼是什么意思| 心气虚吃什么药| 为什么家里蟑螂特别多| 金牛座和什么星座最配| 吐司是什么| 苏轼号什么| 早上起来后背疼是什么原因| 厘米为什么叫公分| 辛未日五行属什么| 白带长什么样| 獠牙是什么意思| 作奸犯科是什么意思| 堃读什么| 现在什么最赚钱| 皴是什么意思| 朱红色是什么颜色| 柠檬水什么时候喝最好| 兔子跟什么生肖最配对| 啪啪是什么意思| 手指麻木吃什么药| 气管疼什么原因引起的| 人天是什么意思| 贞操带是什么| 一件代发是什么意思| 插管意味着什么| 梦见鳄鱼是什么预兆| 屁股疼痛是什么原因引起的| 宫颈那囊什么意思| 为什么洗澡后皮肤会痒| 手掌横纹代表什么意思| 暗是什么意思| 脊髓灰质炎是什么病| 贫血吃什么药效果好| 彩头是什么意思| 韩世忠为什么不救岳飞| 常喝柠檬水有什么好处和坏处| 智能电视什么品牌好| 早上醒来手麻是什么原因| 百度Jump to content

[青海]驻厅纪检组召开党风廉政建设协调(扩大)会议

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
百度 也就是说,全半程选手是混合进入相应的分区来排队的。

Virtue ethics (also aretaic ethics,[a][1] from Greek ?ρετ? [aret?]) is a philosophical approach that treats virtue and character as the primary subjects of ethics, in contrast to other ethical systems that put consequences of voluntary acts, principles or rules of conduct, or obedience to divine authority in the primary role.[2]

Virtue ethics is usually contrasted with two other major approaches in ethics, consequentialism and deontology, which make the goodness of outcomes of an action (consequentialism) and the concept of moral duty (deontology) central. While virtue ethics does not necessarily deny the importance to ethics of goodness of states of affairs or of moral duties, it emphasizes virtue and sometimes other concepts, like eudaimonia, to an extent that other ethics theories do not.[citation needed]

Key concepts

[edit]

Virtue and vice

[edit]

In virtue ethics, a virtue is a characteristic disposition to think, feel, and act well in some domain of life.[3] In contrast, a vice is a characteristic disposition to think, feel, and act poorly in some domain of life. Virtues are not everyday habits; they are character traits, in the sense that they are central to someone’s personality and what they are like as a person.

In early versions and some modern versions of virtue ethics, a virtue is defined as a character trait that promotes or exhibits human "flourishing and well being" in the person who exhibits it.[4] Some modern versions of virtue ethics do not define virtues in terms of well being or flourishing, and some go so far as to define virtues as traits that tend to promote some other good that is defined independently of the virtues, thereby subsuming virtue ethics under (or somehow merging it with) consequentialist ethics.[5]

To Aristotle, a virtue was not a skill that made you better able to achieve eudaimonia but was itself an expression of eudaimonia[6]

Virtue and emotion

[edit]

In ancient Greek and modern eudaimonic virtue ethics, virtues and vices are complex dispositions that involve both affective and intellectual components.[7] That is, they are dispositions that involve both being able to reason well about the right thing to do (see below on phronesis), and also to engage emotions and feelings correctly.

For example, a generous person can reason well about when and how to help people, and such a person also helps people with pleasure and without conflict. In this, virtuous people are contrasted not only with vicious people (who reason poorly about what to do and are emotionally attached to the wrong things) and with the incontinent (who are tempted by their feelings into doing the wrong thing even though they know what is right), but also with the merely continent (whose emotions tempt them toward doing the wrong thing but whose strength of will lets them do what they know is right).

According to Rosalind Hursthouse, in Aristotelian virtue ethics, the emotions have moral significance because "virtues (and vices) are all dispositions not only to act, but to feel emotions, as reactions as well as impulses to action... [and] In the person with the virtues, these emotions will be felt on the right occasions, toward the right people or objects, for the right reasons, where 'right' means 'correct'..."[8]

Phronesis and eudaimonia

[edit]

Phronesis (φρ?νησι?; prudence, practical virtue, or practical wisdom) is an acquired trait that enables its possessor to identify the best thing to do in any given situation.[9] Unlike theoretical wisdom, practical reason results in action or decision.[10] As John McDowell puts it, practical wisdom involves a "perceptual sensitivity" to what a situation requires.[11]

Eudaimonia (ε?δαιμον?α) is a state variously translated from Greek as 'well-being', 'happiness', 'blessedness', and in the context of virtue ethics, 'human flourishing'.[12] Eudaimonia in this sense is not a subjective, but an objective, state.[citation needed] It characterizes the well-lived life.

According to Aristotle, the most prominent exponent of eudaimonia in the Western philosophical tradition, eudaimonia defines the goal of human life. It consists of exercising the characteristic human quality—reason—as the soul's most proper and nourishing activity. In his Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle, like Plato before him, argued that the pursuit of eudaimonia is an "activity of the soul in accordance with perfect virtue",[13]:?I? which further could only properly be exercised in the characteristic human community—the polis or city-state.[14]

Although eudaimonia was first popularized by Aristotle, it now belongs to the tradition of virtue theories generally.[15] For the virtue theorist, eudaimonia describes that state achieved by the person who lives the proper human life, an outcome that can be reached by practicing the virtues. A virtue is a habit or quality that allows the bearer to succeed at his, her, or its purpose. The virtue of a knife, for example, is sharpness; among the virtues of a racehorse is speed. Thus, to identify the virtues for human beings, one must have an account of what is the human purpose.

Not all modern virtue ethics theories are eudaimonic; some propose another end in place of eudaimonia, while others are non-teleological: that is, they do not account for virtues in terms of the results that the practice of the virtues produce or tend to produce.[16]

History of virtue

[edit]

Like much of the Western tradition, virtue theory originated in ancient Greek philosophy.

Virtue ethics began with Socrates, and was subsequently developed further by Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics.[17] Virtue ethics concentrates on the character of the individual, rather than the acts (or consequences thereof) of the individual. There is debate among adherents of virtue ethics concerning what specific virtues are praiseworthy. However, most theorists agree that ethics is demonstrated by the practice of virtues.

Plato and Aristotle's treatments of virtues are not the same. Plato believes virtue is effectively an end to be sought, for which a friend might be a useful means. Aristotle states that the virtues function more as means to safeguard human relations, particularly authentic friendship, without which one's quest for happiness is frustrated.

Discussion of what were known as the four cardinal virtueswisdom, justice, fortitude, and temperance—can be found in Plato's Republic. The virtues also figure prominently in Aristotle's ethical theory found in Nicomachean Ethics.[13]

Virtue theory was inserted into the study of history by moralistic historians such as Livy, Plutarch, and Tacitus. The Greek idea of the virtues was passed on in Roman philosophy through Cicero and later incorporated into Christian moral theology by Ambrose of Milan. During the scholastic period, the most comprehensive consideration of the virtues from a theological perspective was provided by Thomas Aquinas in his Summa Theologiae and his Commentaries on the Nicomachean Ethics.[18]

After the Reformation, Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics continued to be the main authority for the discipline of ethics at Protestant universities until the late seventeenth century, with over fifty Protestant commentaries published on the Nicomachean Ethics before 1682.[19]

Though the tradition receded into the background of European philosophical thought in the next few centuries, the term "virtue" remained current during this period, and in fact appears prominently in the tradition of classical republicanism or classical liberalism. This tradition was prominent in the intellectual life of 16th-century Italy, as well as 17th- and 18th-century Britain and America. The term "virtue" appears frequently in the work of Tomás Fernández de Medrano, Niccolò Machiavelli, David Hume, the republicans of the English Civil War period, the 18th-century English Whigs, and the prominent figures among the Scottish Enlightenment and the American Founding Fathers.

Contemporary "aretaic turn"

[edit]

Although some Enlightenment philosophers (e.g. Hume) continued to emphasise the virtues, with the ascendancy of utilitarianism and deontological ethics, virtue theory moved to the margins of Western philosophy. The contemporary revival of virtue theory is frequently traced to the philosopher Elizabeth Anscombe's 1958 essay "Modern Moral Philosophy".[20] Following this:

The aretaic turn in moral philosophy is paralleled by analogous developments in other philosophical disciplines. One of these is epistemology, where a distinctive virtue epistemology was developed by Linda Zagzebski and others. In political theory, there has been discussion of "virtue politics", and in legal theory, there is a small but growing body of literature on virtue jurisprudence. The aretaic turn also exists in American constitutional theory, where proponents argue for an emphasis on virtue and vice of constitutional adjudicators[clarification needed].[citation needed]

Aretaic approaches to morality, epistemology, and jurisprudence have been the subject of intense debates. One criticism focuses on the problem of guidance; one opponent, Robert Louden in his article "Some Vices of Virtue Ethics", questions whether the idea of a virtuous moral actor, believer, or judge can provide the guidance necessary for action, belief formation, or the resolution of legal disputes.[32]

Lists of virtues

[edit]

There are several lists of virtues. Socrates argued that virtue is knowledge, which suggests that there is really only one virtue.[33] The Stoics identified four cardinal virtues: wisdom, justice, courage, and temperance. Wisdom is subdivided into good sense, good calculation, quick-wittedness, discretion, and resourcefulness. Justice is subdivided into piety, honesty, equity, and fair dealing. Courage is subdivided into endurance, confidence, high-mindedness, cheerfulness, and industriousness. Temperance or moderation is subdivided into good discipline, seemliness, modesty, and self-control.[34]

John McDowell argues that virtue is a "perceptual capacity" to identify how one ought to act, and that all particular virtues are merely "specialized sensitivities" to a range of reasons for acting.[35]

Aristotle's list

[edit]

Aristotle identifies 12 virtues that demonstrate a person is performing their human function well.[13] He distinguished virtues pertaining to emotion and desire from those relating to the mind.[13]:?II? The first he calls moral virtues, and the second intellectual virtues (though both are "moral" in the modern sense of the word).

Moral virtues

[edit]

Aristotle suggested that each moral virtue was a golden mean between two corresponding vices, one of excess and one of deficiency. Each intellectual virtue is a mental skill or habit by which the mind arrives at truth, affirming what is or denying what is not.[13]:?VI? In the Nicomachean Ethics. he discusses 11 moral virtues:

Dimension Excess Golden mean Deficiency
Fear and confidence Rashness Courage in the face of fear[13]:?III.6–9? Cowardice
Pleasure and pain Self-indulgence Temperance in the face of pleasure and pain[13]:?III.10–12? Insensibility
Getting and spending (minor) Prodigality Liberality with wealth and possessions[13]:?IV.1? Illiberality
Getting and spending (major) Vulgarity Magnificence with great wealth and possessions[13]:?IV.2? Pettiness
Honor and dishonor (major) Vanity Magnanimity with great honors[13]:?IV.3? Pusillanimity
Honor and dishonor (minor) Empty vanity Proper ambition with normal honors[13]:?IV.4? Unambitiousness
Anger Irascibility Patience[13]:?IV.5? Lack of spirit
Self-expression Boastfulness Honesty with self-expression[13]:?IV.7? False modesty
Conversation Buffoonery Wittiness in conversation[13]:?IV.8? Boorishness
Social conduct Obsequiousness Friendliness in social conduct[13]:?IV.6? Cantankerousness
Indignation Envy Justice and righteous indignation in the face of injury[13]:?IV.5? Spitefulness

Intellectual virtues

[edit]
  1. Nous (intelligence), which apprehends fundamental truths (such as definitions, self-evident principles)[13]:?VI.11?
  2. Episteme (science), which is skill with inferential reasoning (such as proofs, syllogisms, demonstrations)[13]:?VI.6?
  3. Sophia (theoretical wisdom), which combines fundamental truths with valid, necessary inferences to reason well about unchanging truths.[13]:?VI.5?

Aristotle also mentions several other traits:

  • Gnome (good sense) – passing judgment, "sympathetic understanding"[13]:?VI.11?
  • Synesis (understanding) – comprehending what others say, does not issue commands
  • Phronesis (practical wisdom) – knowledge of what to do, knowledge of changing truths, issues commands[13]:?VI.8?
  • Techne (art, craftsmanship)[13]:?VI.4?

Aristotle's list is not the only list, however. As Alasdair MacIntyre observed in After Virtue, thinkers as diverse as Homer, the authors of the New Testament, Thomas Aquinas, and Benjamin Franklin have all proposed lists.[36] Walter Kaufmann proposed as the four cardinal virtues: ambition/humility ("humbition"), love, courage, and honesty.[37]

Criticisms

[edit]

Proponents of virtue theory[who?] sometimes argue that a central feature of a virtue is its universal applicability. In other words, any character trait defined as a virtue must reasonably be universally regarded as a virtue for all people. According to this view, it is inconsistent to claim, for example, servility as a female virtue, while at the same time not proposing it as a male one.[38]

Other proponents of virtue theory, notably Alasdair MacIntyre, respond to this objection by arguing that any account of the virtues must indeed be generated out of the community in which those virtues are to be practiced: the very word ethics implies ethos. That is to say that the virtues are, and necessarily must be, grounded in a particular time and place. What counts as a virtue in 4th-century BCE Athens would be a ludicrous guide to proper behaviour in 21st-century CE Toronto and vice versa. To take this view does not necessarily commit one to the argument that accounts of the virtues must therefore be static: moral activity—that is, attempts to contemplate and practice the virtues—can provide the cultural resources that allow people to change, albeit slowly, the ethos of their own societies.

MacIntyre appears to take this position in his seminal work on virtue ethics, After Virtue.

Another objection[whose?] to virtue theory is that virtue ethics does not focus on what sorts of actions are morally permitted and which ones are not, but rather on what sort of qualities someone ought to foster in order to become a good person. In other words, while some virtue theorists[who?] may not condemn, for example, murder as an inherently immoral or impermissible sort of action, they may argue that someone who commits a murder is severely lacking in several important virtues, such as compassion and fairness. Still, antagonists of the theory[who?] often object that this particular feature of the theory makes virtue ethics useless as a universal norm of acceptable conduct suitable as a base for legislation[citation needed]. Some virtue theorists[who?] concede this point, but respond by opposing the very notion of legitimate legislative authority instead, effectively advocating some form of anarchism as the political ideal.[citation needed] Other virtue theorists[who?] argue that laws should be made by virtuous legislators, and still another group argue that it is possible to base a judicial system on the moral notion of virtues rather than rules. Aristotle himself saw his Nicomachean Ethics as a prequel for his Politics and felt that the point of politics was to create the fertile soil for a virtuous citizenry to develop in, and that one purpose of virtue was that it helps you to contribute to a healthy polis.[13]:?X.9?[14]

Some virtue theorists[who?] might respond to this overall objection with the notion of a "bad act" also being an act characteristic of vice.[citation needed] That is to say that those acts that do not aim at virtue, or that stray from virtue, would constitute our conception of "bad behavior". Although not all virtue ethicists agree to this notion, this is one way the virtue ethicist can re-introduce the concept of the "morally impermissible". One could raise an objection that he is committing an argument from ignorance by postulating that what is not virtuous is unvirtuous. In other words, just because an action or person 'lacks of evidence' for virtue does not, all else constant, imply that said action or person is unvirtuous.

Subsumed in deontology and utilitarianism

[edit]

Martha Nussbaum suggested that while virtue ethics is often considered to be anti-Enlightenment, "suspicious of theory and respectful of the wisdom embodied in local practices",[39] it is actually neither fundamentally distinct from, nor does it qualify as a rival approach to deontology and utilitarianism. She argues that philosophers from these two Enlightenment traditions often include theories of virtue. She pointed out that Kant's "Doctrine of Virtue" (in The Metaphysics of Morals) "covers most of the same topics as do classical Greek theories", "that he offers a general account of virtue, in terms of the strength of the will in overcoming wayward and selfish inclinations; that he offers detailed analyses of standard virtues such as courage and self-control, and of vices, such as avarice, mendacity, servility, and pride; that, although in general, he portrays inclination as inimical to virtue, he also recognizes that sympathetic inclinations offer crucial support to virtue, and urges their deliberate cultivation."[39]

Nussbaum also points to considerations of virtue by utilitarians such as Henry Sidgwick (The Methods of Ethics), Jeremy Bentham (The Principles of Morals and Legislation), and John Stuart Mill, who writes of moral development as part of an argument for the moral equality of women (The Subjection of Women). She argues that contemporary virtue ethicists such as Alasdair MacIntyre, Bernard Williams, Philippa Foot, and John McDowell have few points of agreement and that the common core of their work does not represent a break from Kant.

Kantian critique

[edit]

Immanuel Kant's position on virtue ethics is contested. Those who argue that Kantian deontology conflicts with virtue ethics include Alasdair MacIntyre, Philippa Foot, and Bernard Williams.[40] In the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals and the Critique of Practical Reason, Immanuel Kant offers many different criticisms of ethical frameworks and against moral theories before him.[citation needed] Kant rarely mentioned Aristotle by name but did not exclude his moral philosophy of virtue ethics from his critique. Many Kantian arguments against virtue ethics claim that virtue ethics is inconsistent, or sometimes that it is not a real moral theory at all.[41]

In "What Is Virtue Ethics All About?",[42] Gregory Velazco y Trianosky identified the key points of divergence between virtue ethicists and what he called "neo-Kantianism", in the form these nine neo-Kantian moral assertions:

  1. The crucial moral question is "what is it right/obligatory to do?"
  2. Moral judgments are those that concern the rightness of actions.
  3. Such judgments take the form of rules or principles.
  4. Such rules or principles are universal, not respecting persons.
  5. They are not based on some concept of human good that is independent of moral goodness.
  6. They take the form of categorical imperatives that can be justified independently of the desires of the person they apply to.
  7. They are motivating; they can compel action in an agent, also independently of that agent's desires.
  8. An action, in order to be morally virtuous, must be motivated by this sort of moral judgment (not, for example, merely coincidentally aligned with it).
  9. The virtuousness of a character trait, or virtue, derives from the relationship that trait has to moral judgments, rules, and principles.

Trianosky says that modern sympathizers with virtue ethics almost all reject neo-Kantian claim #1, and many of them also reject certain of the other claims.

Utopianism and pluralism

[edit]

Robert B. Louden criticizes virtue ethics on the basis that it promotes a form of unsustainable utopianism. Trying to arrive at a single set of virtues is immensely difficult in contemporary societies as, according to Louden, they contain "more ethnic, religious, and class groups than did the moral community which Aristotle theorized about" with each of these groups having "not only its own interests but its own set of virtues as well". Louden notes in passing that MacIntyre, a supporter of virtue-based ethics, has grappled with this in After Virtue but that ethics cannot dispense with building rules around acts and rely only on discussing the moral character of persons.[43]

Topics in virtue ethics

[edit]

Virtue ethics as a category

[edit]

Virtue contrasts with deontological and consequentialist ethics; the three are the most predominant contemporary normative-ethical theories. Deontological ethics, sometimes referred to as duty ethics, emphasizes adherence to ethical principles or duties. How these duties are defined, however, is often a subject of debate. One rule scheme used by deontologists is divine command theory. Deontology also depends upon meta-ethical realism in postulating the existence of moral absolutes, regardless of circumstances. Immanuel Kant is considered a foremost theorist of deontological ethics.

The next predominant school of thought in normative ethics is consequentialism. While deontology emphasizes doing one's duty, consequentialism bases the morality of an action on its outcome. Instead of saying that one has a moral duty to abstain from murder, a consequentialist would say that we should abstain from murder because it has undesirable effects. The main contention is what outcomes should (or can) be identified as objectively desirable.

John Stuart Mill's greatest happiness principle is a commonly-adopted criterion of what is objectively desirable. Mill asserts that the desirability of an action is the net amount of happiness it brings, the number of people it brings happiness to, and the duration of that happiness. He tries to delineate classes of happiness, some preferable to others, but classifying such a concept is difficult.

A virtue ethicist identifies virtues (also known as desirable characteristics) that a good person embodies. Exhibiting these virtues is the aim of ethics, and one's actions are a reflection of one's virtues. To the virtue philosopher, action cannot be used as a demarcation of morality because a virtue encompasses more than a selection of an action; it is a way of being that leads the person exhibiting the virtue to consistently make certain types of choices. There is disagreement in virtue ethics about what are, and what are not, virtues. There are also difficulties in identifying the "virtuous" action to take in all circumstances, and how to define a virtue.

Consequentialist and deontological theories often still employ the term virtue in a restricted sense: as a tendency (or disposition) to adhere to the system's principles or rules. In those theories, virtue is secondary and the principles (or rules) are primary. These differing senses of what constitutes virtue are a potential source of confusion.[44] Dogmatic claims about the purpose of human life, or about what a good life is for human beings, are typically controversial.

Virtue and politics

[edit]

Virtue theory emphasizes Aristotle's belief in the polis as the acme of political organization,[citation needed] and the role of the virtues in enabling human beings to flourish in that environment. In contrast, classical republicanism emphasizes Tacitus's concern that power and luxury can corrupt individuals and destroy liberty, as Tacitus perceived in the transformation of the Roman Republic into the Roman Empire. Virtue for classical republicans is a shield against this sort of corruption and a means to preserve the good life one has, rather than a means by which to achieve the good life one does not yet have. Another way to put the distinction between the two traditions is that virtue ethics relies on Aristotle's fundamental distinction between the human-being-as-he-is from the human-being-as-he-should-be, while classical republicanism relies on the Tacitean distinction of the risk-of-becoming.[45]

Virtue ethics has a number of contemporary applications:

Social and political philosophy

Within the field of social ethics, Deirdre McCloskey argues that virtue ethics can provide a basis for a balanced approach to understanding capitalism and capitalist societies.[46][47]

Education

Within the field of philosophy of education, James Page argues that virtue ethics can provide a rationale and foundation for peace education.[48]

Health care and medical ethics

Thomas Alured Faunce argued that whistleblowing in healthcare settings would be more respected within clinical governance pathways if it had a firmer academic foundation in virtue ethics.[49] He called for whistleblowing to be expressly supported in the UNESCO Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights.[50] Barry Schwartz argues that "practical wisdom" is an antidote to much of the inefficient and inhumane bureaucracy of modern health care systems.[51]

Technology and the virtues

In her book Technology and the Virtues,[52] Shannon Vallor proposed a series of "technomoral" virtues that people need to cultivate in order to flourish in our socio-technological world: Honesty (Respecting Truth), Self-control (Becoming the Author of Our Desires), Humility (Knowing What We Do Not Know), Justice (Upholding Rightness), Courage (Intelligent Fear and Hope), Empathy (Compassionate Concern for Others), Care (Loving Service to Others), Civility (Making Common Cause), Flexibility (Skillful Adaptation to Change), Perspective (Holding on to the Moral Whole), and Magnanimity (Moral Leadership and Nobility of Spirit).

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ Pronounced /??r??te?.?k/.

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Carr, David; Steutel, Jan, eds. (1999). Virtue Ethics and Moral Education. Routledge. p. 22. ISBN 9780415170734.
  2. ^ Statman, Daniel (1997). "Introduction to Virtue Ethics". Virtue Ethics: A Critical Reader. Edinburgh University Press. p. 7. ISBN 0878402217. [Virtue Ethics] refers to a rather new (or renewed) approach to ethics, according to which the basic judgments in ethics are judgments about character.
  3. ^
  4. ^ Statman, Daniel (1997). "Introduction to Virtue Ethics". Virtue Ethics: A Critical Reader. Edinburgh University Press. p. 8. ISBN 0878402217. Virtues are viewed as necessary conditions for, or as constitutive elements of, human flourishing and wellbeing.
  5. ^ Trianosky, Gregory Velazco y (1997). "What is Virtue Ethics All About?". In Statman, Daniel (ed.). Virtue Ethics: A Critical Reader. Edinburgh University Press. p. 48. ISBN 0878402217. What is surprising today is how many of the most influential writers on the virtues today in fact defend some sort of teleological if not specifically utilitarian answer.
  6. ^ Trianosky, Gregory Velazco y (1997). "What is Virtue Ethics All About?". In Statman, Daniel (ed.). Virtue Ethics: A Critical Reader. Edinburgh University Press. p. 47. ISBN 0878402217. [Aristotle regards virtue as] a constitutive element of the human good rather than merely a means to its attainment.
  7. ^ Annas, Julia (1993). The Morality of Happiness. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 48–49. ISBN 0-19-507999-X.
  8. ^ Hursthouse, Rosalind (1997). "Virtue Ethics and the Emotions". In Statman, Daniel (ed.). Virtue Ethics: A Critical Reader. Edinburgh University Press. p. 108. ISBN 0878402217.
  9. ^ Pincoffs, Edmund (1971). "Quandary ethics". Mind. 80 (320): 552–571. doi:10.1093/mind/LXXX.320.552.
  10. ^ Kraut, Richard (2025-08-06). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Aristotle's Ethics (Spring 2016 ed.). Archived from the original on 2025-08-06. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  11. ^ McDowell, John (1979). "Virtue and Reason". The Monist. 62 (3): 331–350. doi:10.5840/monist197962319.
  12. ^ Pojman, L.P.; Fieser, J. (2009). "Virtue Theory". Ethics: Discovering Right and Wrong (6th ed.). Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth. pp. 146–169.
  13. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w Dubey, Damayanti (December 31, 2021). "12 Virtues of Aristotle". evolveinc.io.
  14. ^ a b Aristotle. Politics.
  15. ^ Hursthouse, Rosalind (8 Dec 2016). "Virtue Ethics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. Archived from the original on 23 September 2018. Retrieved 11 May 2020. Although modern virtue ethics does not have to take a 'neo-Aristotelian' or eudaimonist form..., almost any modern version still shows that its roots are in ancient Greek philosophy by the employment of three concepts derived from it. These are arête (excellence or virtue), phronesis (practical or moral wisdom) and eudaimonia (usually translated as happiness or flourishing).
  16. ^ Statman, Daniel (1997). "Introduction to Virtue Ethics". Virtue Ethics: A Critical Reader. Edinburgh University Press. p. 11. ISBN 0878402217. [I]t is important to notice (1.) that virtue ethics is not necessarily tied to the notion of wellbeing; and (2.) that according to some philosophers, virtue ethics is necessarily, or at least typically, of a non-teleological nature.
  17. ^
  18. ^
    • Aquinas, Thomas (1485). Summa Theologica.
    • Aquinas, Thomas (1272). Commentary on the Ten Books of Ethics.
  19. ^ Sytsma, David (2021). "Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics and Protestantism". Academia Letters. 1650: 1–8. doi:10.20935/AL1650. S2CID 237798959.
  20. ^ Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958). "Modern Moral Philosophy". Philosophy. 33 (124): 1–19. doi:10.1017/s0031819100037943. JSTOR 3749051. S2CID 197875941.
  21. ^ Stocker, Michael (1976). "The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories". The Journal of Philosophy. 73 (14): 453–466. doi:10.2307/2025782. JSTOR 2025782.
  22. ^ Foot, Philippa (1978). Virtues and Vices. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. ISBN 0631127496.
  23. ^
  24. ^ Ricoeur, Paul (1992) [1990]. Oneself as Another. Translated by Blamey, Kathleen. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0-226-71329-6.
  25. ^ Taylor, Richard (2002) [1991]. Virtue Ethics An Introduction. New York: Prometheus Books. ISBN 9781573929431.
  26. ^ Virtue Ethics an Introduction.Taylor, Richard. Promethious Books, New York, 2002, See Foreword by John Donnelly, University of San Diego p. xiii-xiv, isbn 1-57392-943-3 on Google Books
  27. ^ Crisp, Roger; Slote, Michael (1997). Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  28. ^ Annas, Julia (1993). The Morality of Happiness. Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-509652-5.
  29. ^ Becker, Lawrence C. (1998). A New Stoicism. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. p. 30. ISBN 978-0691009643.
  30. ^ Hursthouse, Rosalind (1999). On Virtue Ethics. Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-924799-4.
  31. ^ Goleman, Daniel (1995). Emotional Intelligence: Why It Can Matter More Than IQ. Aristotle's Challenge, pp. xix–xxiv: Bantam Books. ISBN 978-0-553-38371-3.
  32. ^ Louden, Robert B. (1984). "On some vices of virtue ethics". American Philosophical Quarterly. 21 (3): 227–236.
  33. ^ Plato, Meno.
  34. ^
    • Stephens, William O. "Stoic Ethics". www.iep.utm.edu. Retrieved 14 February 2023.
    • Cicero, Marcus Tullius. "De Officiis" [On Moral Duties]. www.oll.libertyfund.org. Retrieved 14 February 2023.
  35. ^ McDowell, John (1979). "Virtue and reason". The Monist. 62 (3): 331–350. doi:10.5840/monist197962319.
  36. ^ MacIntyre, Alasdair (1981). After Virtue. Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press. Chapter 14. ISBN 0-268-00594-X.
  37. ^ Kaufmann, Walter (1961). The Faith Of A Heretic. Doubleday & Co. pp. 317–338. doi:10.1515/9781400866168-013.
  38. ^ Rachels, James, Stuart (2023). The Elements of Moral Philosophy (10th ed.). McGraw Hill LLC. pp. 169–184. ISBN 978-1-265-23718-9.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  39. ^ a b Nussbaum, Martha C. (1999). "Virtue Ethics: A Misleading Category?". The Journal of Ethics. 3 (3): 163–201. doi:10.1023/A:1009877217694. JSTOR 25115613. S2CID 141533832.
  40. ^ MacIntyre, Alasdair (1981). After Virtue. Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press. pp. 42, 112. ISBN 0-268-00594-X.
  41. ^ Sullivan, Roger J. (1974). "The Kantian Critique of Aristotle's Moral Philosophy: An Appraisal". The Review of Metaphysics. 28 (1): 24–53. JSTOR 20126582.
  42. ^ Trianosky, Gregory Velazco y (1997). "What is Virtue Ethics All About?". In Statman, Daniel (ed.). Virtue Ethics: A Critical Reader. Edinburgh University Press. pp. 47–55. ISBN 0878402217.
  43. ^ Louden, Robert B. (July 1984). "On Some Vices of Virtue Ethics". American Philosophical Quarterly. 21 (3): 227–236. JSTOR 20014051.
  44. ^ Statman, Daniel (1997). "Introduction to Virtue Ethics". Virtue Ethics: A Critical Reader. Edinburgh University Press. p. 7. ISBN 0878402217. [A] view shared by both deontologists and utilitarians... [is that] the value of character traits is dependent on the value of the conduct that these traits tend to produce, and it is the concept of right behavior that it theoretically prior, not that of virtue. In reversing the order of justification, virtue ethics is calling for a real revolution in ethical thought...
  45. ^ Pocock, J.G.A. (1975). The Machiavellian Moment. Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-11472-2. LCCN 2002112936.
  46. ^ McCloskey, Deirdre N. (2007). The Bourgeois Virtues. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-55664-2.
  47. ^ McCloskey, Deirdre N. (2015). "Bourgeois Virtue". Wiley Encyclopedia of Management. pp. 1–2. doi:10.1002/9781118785317.weom020101. ISBN 9781118785317.
  48. ^ Page, James; Page, James Smith (2008). Peace Education: Exploring Ethical and Philosophical Foundations. Information Age Pub Incorporated. ISBN 978-1-59311-889-1.
  49. ^
    • Faunce, T.A. (2004). "Developing and Teaching the Virtue-Ethics Foundations of Healthcare Whistle Blowing". Monash Bioethics Review. 23 (4): 41–55. doi:10.1007/BF03351419. PMID 15688511. S2CID 195243797.
    • Faunce, T.A.; Jefferys, S. (2007). "Whistleblowing and Scientific Misconduct: Renewing Legal and Virtue Ethics Foundations". Journal of Medicine and Law. 26 (3): 567–584. PMID 17970253.
  50. ^ Faunce, T. A.; Nasu, H. (23 April 2009). "Normative Foundations of Technology Transfer and Transnational Benefit Principles in the UNESCO Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights". Journal of Medicine and Philosophy. 34 (3). Oxford University Press (OUP): 296–321. doi:10.1093/jmp/jhp021. ISSN 0360-5310. PMID 19395367.
  51. ^ Schwartz, Barry (16 February 2009). "Our loss of wisdom". www.ted.com. Archived from the original on 2025-08-06. Retrieved 2025-08-06.
  52. ^ Technology and the Virtues: A Philosophical Guide to a Future Worth Wanting. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press. 2016. ISBN 978-0190498511.

Further reading

[edit]
  • Yu, Jiyuan (1998). "Virtue: Confucius and Aristotle". Philosophy East and West. 48 (2): 323–47. doi:10.2307/1399830. JSTOR 1399830.
  • Devettere, Raymond J. (2002). Introduction to Virtue Ethics. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.
  • Taylor, Richard (2002). An Introduction to Virtue Ethics. Amherst: Prometheus Books.
  • Darwall, Stephen, ed. (2003). Virtue Ethics. Oxford: B. Blackwell.
  • Swanton, Christine (2003). Virtue Ethics: a Pluralistic View. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Gardiner, Stephen M., ed. (2005). Virtue Ethics, Old and New. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • Russell, Daniel C., ed. (2013). The Cambridge Companion to Virtue Ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press.
[edit]
印记是什么意思 增强ct是什么意思 什么书什么画 花裙子配什么上衣好看 猴与什么属相相配最好
强度是什么意思 balco是什么牌子手表 玉戴久了会有什么变化 小白加小白等于什么 手脱皮是缺什么维生素
脚麻木是什么原因引起的 什么是负离子 什么的舞蹈 武火是什么意思 眼花缭乱什么意思
choker什么意思 什么是中暑 失不出头念什么 闭门思过是什么意思 冥寿是什么意思
经常吃土豆有什么好处hcv7jop5ns0r.cn 女性多囊是什么意思hcv9jop4ns5r.cn 胸疼应该挂什么科hcv8jop7ns8r.cn 夏天穿什么鞋hcv8jop7ns7r.cn 手术后吃什么最有营养hcv8jop8ns3r.cn
ecco什么牌子hcv7jop7ns3r.cn 一什么千什么hcv8jop8ns5r.cn 射手和什么星座最配hcv7jop4ns7r.cn 杂合变异是什么意思hcv9jop5ns9r.cn 1.7号是什么星座1949doufunao.com
海绵肾是什么意思hcv8jop3ns5r.cn 新生儿超敏c反应蛋白高说明什么hcv8jop7ns5r.cn 煎饼果子的果子是什么hcv9jop2ns7r.cn 梦见很多狗是什么意思hcv9jop3ns1r.cn 官杀是什么imcecn.com
什么是钓鱼网站hcv7jop6ns4r.cn 股骨头坏死有什么好办法治疗吗hcv8jop5ns8r.cn 大腿根部痒用什么药膏hcv8jop0ns9r.cn 晚上肚子疼是什么原因hcv7jop6ns4r.cn 怀孕初期能吃什么不能吃什么hcv8jop6ns9r.cn
百度